1-20 of 111 Search Results for

deliberative

Follow your search
Access your saved searches in your account

Would you like to receive an alert when new items match your search?
Close Modal
Sort by
Journal Article
The Philosophical Review (2011) 120 (1): 1–41.
Published: 01 January 2011
... view that 'ought' always expresses this relation—adherents of the naive view are happy to allow that 'ought' also has an evaluative sense, on which it means, roughly, that were things ideal, some proposition would be the case. What is important to the naive view is that there is also a deliberative...
Journal Article
The Philosophical Review (2012) 121 (2): 209–239.
Published: 01 April 2012
... deliberation and Railton 2009 on practical deliber- ation.)3 They are mental actions, or perhaps mental actions conducted issue; and Railton 2004, 2009, in which the first steps of the present argument are taken (in the jargon we deploy later in this article, Railton makes the regress argument against...
Journal Article
The Philosophical Review (2011) 120 (3): 383–421.
Published: 01 July 2011
..., Alexander maintains that deliberation is carried out on the assumption that we have the power also to do the opposite of what we in fact do [hoˆs exousian echonti tou prattein kai ta anti- keimena] For concerning each of the things that fall under the delib- eration...
Journal Article
The Philosophical Review (2000) 109 (4): 583–586.
Published: 01 October 2000
... important, which repay close study. One of the best-worked-out parts of the book is chapter 2 on Williams on internal and external reasons. Hampton argues that commentators have failed to notice a distinction between two of Williams’s theses: (a) that any reason must be “deliberatively...
Journal Article
The Philosophical Review (2000) 109 (4): 545–581.
Published: 01 October 2000
... delib- 15Suppose,for example, that I am very thirsty and someone hands me a large, cool drink. Unbeknownst to me the drink is poisoned. It is plau- sible to say that having this drink is not in my interest, despite the fact that I very much want it. Thus, sometimes wanting something...
Journal Article
The Philosophical Review (2005) 114 (4): 497–534.
Published: 01 October 2005
... that the deliberative question whether to believe that p is transparent to the question whether p. This argument raises various questions. Is there such a thing as deliberating whether to believe? Is the transparency of the deliberative question whether to believe that p the same as the transparency of the factual...
Journal Article
The Philosophical Review (2022) 131 (4): 519–523.
Published: 01 October 2022
...) and the “practical thinking” view (currently enjoying prominence), and demonstrates convincingly that neither account for the three criteria that Schapiro puts forth: (1) inclinations exert asymmetric volitional pressure ; (2) inclinations are nonvoluntary ; (3) inclinations play a deliberative role...
Journal Article
The Philosophical Review (2003) 112 (4): 447–482.
Published: 01 October 2003
... questions within the first-personal deliberative perspective; the question whether to believe that p seems to collapse into the question whether p is true. Nor can the explanation for the way we seamlessly move from the former question to the latter question be that it is merely psychologically...
Journal Article
The Philosophical Review (2000) 109 (4): 592–595.
Published: 01 October 2000
... require in deliberation is that specified by the conditional story. 593 The extension of the argument to the case of responsibility, however, is rather less persuasive. Holding someone responsible is not in the first in- stance a deliberative stance, so...
Journal Article
The Philosophical Review (2017) 126 (1): 140–146.
Published: 01 January 2017
... the status quo would not be excluded. To complete his conception of democracy, Pettit goes on to suggest a model of popular control in which control is realized in the long haul by a deliberatively constituted decision procedure. He develops this model by rejecting the obvious possibility...
Journal Article
The Philosophical Review (2004) 113 (2): 249–267.
Published: 01 April 2004
...- deliberative, and (4) the use made by Moran of Sartre. In each case I have some comments to make on the scope of Moran’s treatment of the topic. These four themes do not by any means exhaust the content of the book, and my discussion of them will convey all too little of the subtlety of Moran’s analyses...
Journal Article
The Philosophical Review (2004) 113 (2): 269–271.
Published: 01 April 2004
... psychology on understanding of the first person, (2) the issue of realism or idealism regarding the objects of self-knowledge, (3) Moran’s conception of the practical- deliberative, and (4) the use made by Moran of Sartre. In each case I have some comments to make on the scope of Moran’s treatment...
Journal Article
The Philosophical Review (2004) 113 (2): 272–275.
Published: 01 April 2004
... psychology on understanding of the first person, (2) the issue of realism or idealism regarding the objects of self-knowledge, (3) Moran’s conception of the practical- deliberative, and (4) the use made by Moran of Sartre. In each case I have some comments to make on the scope of Moran’s treatment...
Journal Article
The Philosophical Review (2004) 113 (2): 275–278.
Published: 01 April 2004
...) the issue of realism or idealism regarding the objects of self-knowledge, (3) Moran’s conception of the practical- deliberative, and (4) the use made by Moran of Sartre. In each case I have some comments to make on the scope of Moran’s treatment of the topic. These four themes do not by any means...
Journal Article
The Philosophical Review (2004) 113 (1): 127–129.
Published: 01 January 2004
... the competing considerations to a common measure of value. … I found it remarkable how often we could reach deliberative closure in the face of this heterogeneity” (7). Despite the fact of pluralism even at the political level, reasonable decisions could be reached. The book is never dull. Galston...
Journal Article
The Philosophical Review (2005) 114 (3): 411–413.
Published: 01 July 2005
.... Otherwise put, the deliberative model does not apply to Thurber’s action. For Schueler, if one does not confuse direct desire explanations with deliberative ones, one is in a position to see that genuine practical reasoning must contain evaluative premises to the effect that some- thing is good...
Journal Article
The Philosophical Review (2006) 115 (2): 169–198.
Published: 01 April 2006
... that he’s playing chess even though he doesn’t care about win- ning. (Here is Korsgaard [4.6.2] employing a similarly tendentious reading of “to delib- erate”: “an agent who is deliberating about what to do cannot completely ignore the Kantian imperatives and still recognizably be deliberating about...
Journal Article
The Philosophical Review (2000) 109 (2): 267–270.
Published: 01 April 2000
.... 267 BOOK REVlEWS responsibility-constituting deliberative processes must be “the agent’s own.” They argue in chapter 7 that there is an essentially historical di- mension to moral responsibility that cannot be captured by purely struc- tural “mesh theories...
Journal Article
The Philosophical Review (2003) 112 (2): 215–245.
Published: 01 April 2003
... states. By contrast, one might understand the good in more objective terms, either as consist- ing in the perfection of one’s essential capacities (for example, one’s rational or deliberative capacities) or as consisting in some list of dis- parate objective goods (for example, knowledge, beauty...
Journal Article
The Philosophical Review (2014) 123 (1): 79–105.
Published: 01 January 2014
... broadly, to include epistemic agents, desiderative agents, and so forth), it must in principle be possible for them to act or form the relevant attitude for that reason —that is, for it to be their reason for doing so—and that they would do so were they to exercise ideally the powers of deliberative...